Rationality, Instinct, and Intuition
When it comes to the means to survival, the dichotomy between rationality and instinct presents itself as the matter of all-or-nothing. That is, the idea is that rationality is deemed to be either best fit for self-preservation or a poor substitute for instinct which is, blessed by evolution, most optimal for promoting prosperity. However, the terms themselves are vague in their everyday usage, causing equivocations and conflations. (Even Kant, within whose tradition I locate my arguments, was vulnerable to this fallacy.) I believe that, once the terms are clarified, rationality would turn out to be much more reliable than instinct. Yet, this is due to the employment of rationality’s protégé, viz., intuition.
Here are the provisional definitions for ‘rationality’
and ‘instinct’.
Rationality: the capacity to impose and follow rules
Instinct: the capacity to respond to stimuli (without involving rule-imposing/following)
If you define instinct broadly merely as the capacity
to respond to stimuli, rationality is then a kind of instinct as the capacity
to respond to stimuli by imposing and following rules. To distinguish
between rationality-qua-instinct and other kinds of instinct, we must define
instinct as that which involves no rule-imposing/following.
Rules are articulated in terms of concepts (codified
in language). In turn, concepts are inferential. Thus, rationality is the
capacity to make inferences by employing linguistic items codifying concepts.
To go by rules is to undertake a conceptual-linguistic framework. Accordingly,
rationality is conceptual-linguistic, and instinct is non-conceptual and
non-linguistic (in the sense that it involves no concept or language at all.)
One of the most essential needs of survival is
reliability. Affordances (tools, machines, data, etc.) are conducive to self-preservation
and prosperity only if they function as expected, for it is through
repeatability and reproducibility could we make use of the affordances to
control and cope with our surroundings. For instance, a thermometer that records
different temperature each time under the same (or similar) circumstances is
useless, i.e., unreliable.
Rules represent the reliable patterns in nature (laws
of nature) as well as in society (conventions). Thus, it would be much more
advantageous to rely on rules than not. For this reason, rationality is the more
reliable means to survival. Of course, in understanding the behavioral patterns
of non-human animals, we do use conceptual codifications. That is, we describe
animals as if they are following rules in their coping. But this is our
problem. There is no guarantee that, tomorrow, bears will hibernate or dogs
will bark at strangers again. Instincts are capricious and is free to respond
to stimuli in whichever way they would like to. Instinctive responses that
happen to be fit for the concerned stimuli enable their subject to survive
another day, and its species are preserved—but purely accidentally. But there
is no reason why the instinct will employ the same response in the next time it
is faced with the same stimulus other than out of luck.
The problem with rationality is that this capacity is
too rigid and often distal. Rigid, because once rules are determined, it is
difficult to overthrow them and find their alternatives. Drawing out patterns
from nature takes time, and codified information is inert. Distal, because the
mind still needs to figure out how to apply rules in real-life
situations. Given the (analytic) rule that water quenches thirst, when and in respect
to what should we apply the concept of water, quenching, and thirst? Of various
possible causal constraints and brute impulses, which ones should we select as following
the patterns of nature?
The rigidity and distality of rationality (and of
conceptuality) often leads one to favor and even glorify instinct over rationality
as instinct is seen to be more flexible and spontaneous. However, I think that
this is a false dichotomy. The given is that instinct is nowhere near the reliability
of rationality, but rationality is too rigid and distal in itself. If so, there
must be a third way out.
The third horn is intuition. It is through (Kantian) intuition
do we make epistemic frictions with the world. Here is the provisional
definition of ‘intuition’.
Intuition: the capacity to respond to stimuli as governed and guided by rules
Intuitions themselves do not impose or intentionally
follow rules. But they can be molded and shaped by conceptual practices as to
be guided in their employment. Thus, in their reports of the world (via
sensibility), intuitions provide us with codified information fit for inferential
activities. Should we change conceptual frameworks for whatever pragmatic or theoretical
needs, intuitions can be retrained accordingly. Since intuitions are still
rule-governed, they are under the spell of concepts. Whether they themselves
are conceptual or merely phenomenological is up for a debate. (Intuitions could
be non-conceptual in the sense that one could be unaware of concepts in employing
intuitions.) However, intuitions are certainly distinguished from instincts.
Intuitions are rationality’s solution to its problems,
for intuitions are more flexible and less distal. Flexible, because intuitions
can be retrained and reshaped. Also, as that through which we make epistemic
frictions with the world, intuitions make empirical reports in the form appropriate
for examining the soundness of our conceptual framework. Less distal, because
intuitions are much more spontaneous and automatic than rationality. Whereas it
takes time for rationality to make judgments about applications of rules every
time it is employed, intuitions can instantaneously apply rules as trained out
of habits.
What must be noted is
that intuitions are not independent of rules. As Kant remarked, “thoughts
without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind.” Intuitions
provide contents, but these contents are sorted and guided by rule-giving
concepts.
Readers of contemporary
philosophy will recognize not only that my view on intuition is Kantian, but
also that it is relevant to various philosophical ideas and debates: the Sellarsian
distinction between ought-to-be and ought-to-do rules, the debate between John
McDowell and Hubert Dreyfus, and the top-down and the bottom-up approach to
perception and thought. In addition, intuition is the bridge between
rationality and virtue ethics (refer to my previous post).
Comments
Post a Comment